Bioethics

Bioethics. PART I: GENERAL ISSUES

1. Introduction: What Is Bioethics? ……………………………………….3

2. Technology, Nature, and Responsibility …………………………..13

3. Ethical Issues and Theories ……………………………………………..28

4. Common Terms Used in Bioethics ………………………………….39

PART II: ISSUES EARLY IN LIFE

5. Abortion ………………………………………………………………………..67

6. Reproductive Technologies ……………………………………………..89

7. Early Diagnosis of Genetic Anomalies …………………………… 107

PART III: ISSUES AT THE END OF LIFE

8. Definitions of Death ……………………………………………………. 129

9. Forgoing and Withdrawing Treatment ………………………….. 144

10. Euthanasia …………………………………………………………………..168

11. Physician-Assisted Suicide ……………………………………………. 184

PART IV: ISSUES IN BIOTECHNOLOGY

12. Genetic Engineering: Nonhuman Organisms …………………201

13. Genetic Engineering: Human Beings ……………………………..231

14. Cell-Based Biotechnologies …………………………………………..250

PART V. OTHER SPECIFIC PROBLEMS

15. Organ and Tissue Transplantation ………………………………..273

16. Research on Human Subjects ………………………………………..290

17. A Whole Earth Ethic …………………………………………………….302

WHAT IS BIOETHICS?

Today the word bioethics is commonplace. Several newsmagazines, television shows, and Web sites have devoted special editions to topics such as stem cell technology, cloning, organ transplantation, in vitro fertilization, and gene therapy. Almost daily, media attention focuses on some particular problem, application, or breakthrough in science that inevitably raises as many problems as it solves.

We have become so used to these discussions and events that we forget that it was only forty years ago that the institute of Society, Ethics and the Life Sciences-as the Hastings Center was known then- was founded.’ In 1965, few knew of the institute, and fewer still understood what its members were talking about. But the role and value of this institute, and others that were to follow in its footsteps, were soon discovered as the major questions of abortion, population control, the allocation of resources, genetic engineering, behavior modification, and all the problems associated with dying began to press in upon us. Discoveries and applications began to outpace our ability to reflect on them, and everyone was reeling from the biological revolution.

We have seen several presidential commissions and advisory boards, an encyclopedia and its revised editions/ numerous journals3 and books,’ several societies, associations, and centers,’ and innumerable conferences all devoted to various problems in bioethics. Courses have spread throughout undergraduate and graduate schools; even graduate programs in bioethics now exist. Bioethicists have appeared as experts in court trials, and journalists frequently cite them in media reports about various dilemmas in health care and the life sciences. Institutional review boards, which examine the ethical dimensions of human research, are present almost everywhere.’ Many hospitals now have in-house ethicists and/or ethics committees to help evaluate a variety of ethical dilemmas that occur in the routine provision of health care.’

Few would have thought that such events could have happened when the first few tentative steps in the ethical examination of issues in health care were being taken in the 1960s. From these early days, commentators generated a wealth of scholarship; and although many problems seem as intractable as they did when first considered, the field has advanced considerably, and we are the beneficiaries of such scholarship.

A number of names have come into use to describe different areas of study in this field. One is

medical ethics. This looks primarily to the study of ethics within the discipline of medicine and the medical profession. Another term is health care ethics, which examines all the various issues in health care, including medical and nursing ethics, as well as public policy and institutional issues. The term organizational ethics sometimes designates ethical discourse concerning institutional issues. When considering the ethics of caring for patients at the bedside, the terms clinical ethics or clinical bioethics are used. We will use the term bioethics, which is a more inclusive term.

Since bioethics examines the ethical issues at both the heart and the cutting edge of technology in health care and the life sciences, the area covered is necessarily broad. This is what makes bioethics as a field of study complex but also exciting. There is a need for many specialties and disciplines because no one field can claim the territory of life. In addition to the potential benefits and harms, we have learned that medical technologies have economic consequences, which raise questions of allocation. Reality-which is itself interdisciplinary-has taught us to be interdisciplinary in our thinking. Similarly, bioethics is teaching us the necessity of genuine interdisciplinary thinking and working. Traditional disciplines that participated in one way or another in the field of bioethics include, for example, theology, philosophy, medicine, law, and biology. One might say that bioethics is a multidisciplinary field carried out through interdisciplinary discourse.

BIOETHICS

When we focus on the first part of the word bioethics- are thrust into the exciting, complex, and often troublesome world of medicine and the life sciences, which includes neuroscience, genetics, and molecular biology. The prefix biocomes from the Greek word for life (bios). Several questions emerge when one thinks about applications of both biotechnology and nanotechnology. This aspect of our topic requires that we study these fields to understand the biological revolution that is occurring around us. While we need be neither experts nor even competent amateurs, we do need to be informed citizens if for no other reason than the developments in these fields have a profound impact on our lives and our society. Thus paying attention to developments in these fields is a critical first step in examining ethical dilemmas in bioethics.

BIOETHICS

The other part of the word-“ethics”-is equally important, for the developments we discuss raise serious and profound dilemmas that challenge our value system as well as the culture supporting those values. The root ethics comes from the Greek word ethike meaning the science of morals or the study of habits.

Ethics, of course, has a problematic reputation. Many regard ethics as the great naysayer and dismiss it out of hand. Others reduce ethical arguments to opinion or taste and refuse to face arguments and conflicts. Still others use carefully developed principles and/or methodologies to consider various values and to tease out hidden conflicts and complex relationships.

Let us present an overview of two methods of ethical decision making that are frequently used in bioethics. The first is a kind of ethics known as deontological ethics. The Greek word deon means duty, obligation, or principle. Deontological ethics is a method of decision making that begins by asking, “What are my duties?” or “What are my obligations?” The correct ethical course is to follow

one’s duties-regardless of where they lead one. One may refer to this as the “Damn the torpedoes, full steam ahead” school of ethics. For once duties or obligations are established, the appropriate actions are clear and must be undertaken regardless of circumstances or outcomes.

A very common example of deontological ethics is the Ten Commandments of the Judeo-Christian religious tradition. The Ten Commandments are basically a set of moral duties that tell what to do or not to do. Biblical writers present them as clear and certain moral guides that mean what they say and say what they mean. They are, after all, the Ten Commandments, not the Ten Suggestions.

The second is a kind of ethics known as teleological ethics. The Greek word telos means end or goal. Thus, in teleological ethics, one’s moral obligations are established, not by an evaluation of obligations, but by an examination of consequences or outcomes of various actions. Thus one name for this kind of ethical theory is consequentialism. This method attempts to predict what will happen if one acts in various ways and to compare these various outcomes against one another. This outcomes-based evaluative process determines what is moral or the right act.

Situation ethics is probably one of the better known of the many variants of consequentialism. Popularized in the mid1960s by Joseph Fletcher, situation ethics requires that we attend seriously to the implications of actualizing our ethical beliefs. Thus situation ethics would argue that it is not enough to do good; one must also know which of the many possible goods is better. Therefore, the basis for right action is found in the particular characteristics of the situation.

Although each of these has the strengths of the ideas on which the methods are based, they both suffer from a limitation: they each have tunnel vision when evaluating means or ends. Deontological ethics typically neglects the outcome of an act and is inattentive to substantive differences in the outcome of our actions or the way an unnuanced act can affect individuals or society. Additionally, deontological ethics typically does not take into account the situation or circumstances in which individuals find themselves. Similarly, in its zeal to attend to the outcomes of our actions, consequentialism neglects to develop a way to evaluate the various outcomes or to compare them against one another. That is, situation ethics says to do that act which produces the best or better outcome. But it has no built-in standard by which to judge or to discriminate between outcomes. Perhaps a viable ethical strategy would be to use the two theories as a dialectical way of evaluating both means and ends. In this way, the theories can be mutually corrective rather than mutually exclusive by being attentive both to our obligations and to various outcomes.

We will explore ethical theories in more detail in chapter 3.

THE ISSUES

One can find the topics we will discuss in this book in the table of contents. As an introduction, the book will present an overview of the issues in the major problem areas of bioethics: abortion, reproductive technology, early (genetic) diagnoses, death and dying, forgoing or withdrawing treatment, euthanasia, physician-assisted suicide, genetic engineering-of plants, animals, and human beings-cell-based biotechnologies (e.g., stem cell technology, cloning, and chimera research), organ transplantation, research on human subjects, and environmental issues.

As you proceed into the book, you will notice that certain questions continue to reappear, certain terms continue to make their significance felt. Certain questions and solutions to problems will raise broader social policy questions. Specific practices call into question fundamental relationships and values. This introduction to bioethics will not examine all these topics or subjects but will frame various questions so that you will have a way of orienting yourself to these broader questions of social policy. For an in-depth examination of these and other topics, we suggest books at the end of each chapter that are relevant for that particular topic.

You will also find any number of Web sites on the Internet relating to bioethics. In November 2007, we ran a Google Web search on “bioethics,” which returned about 4,610,000 hits. Of course, not all of these hits may be trustworthy, good, or reliable. There are several research tools available on the Internet and through libraries. The National Reference Center for Bioethics Literature (NRCBL) at Georgetown University offers a bibliographic search service. Users submit information about the particular topic and project on which they are working, and the NRCBL will return a bibliography of bioethics resources (articles, books, etc.) fulfilling the search criteria. The Web portal for this service is: http://bioethics.georgetown.edu. As the Internet evolves, scholars, students, and others in the field of bioethics will begin to appreciate and distinguish the good resources on the Web from the problematic ones.

To return to our first question-What is bioethics?-let us consider a few definitions. One may define bioethics generally as follows: the systematic exercise, study, and methodology of responsible agents and actions in the life sciences (e.g., biology) and healing arts (e.g., medicine). The Oxford English Dictionary defines bioethics as, “The discipline dealing with ethical questions that arise as a result of advances in medicine and biology.”‘ A biologist by the name of Van Rensselaer Potter first used the term to refer “to a new field devoted to human survival and an improved quality of life, not necessarily or particularly medical in character.”‘ In 1977, the philosopher Samuel Gorovitz defined bioethics as the “critical examination of the moral dimensions of decision-making in health-related contexts and in contexts involving the biological sciences.”” This definition is still a good one for it highlights the interdisciplinary and social dimensions of bioethics. It points us in the right direction as we enter the fascinating, but complex world of bioethics.

DISCUSSION QUESTIONS

1. Why is it necessary to have basic knowledge of both scientific and ethical issues in considering the problems encountered in bioethics?

2. What major bioethical problems have been in the media recently? What are some of their implications?

3. Why must one also consider the social or policy implications of problems in bioethics?

NOTES

1. Albert R. Jonsen, The Birth of Bioethics (New York: Oxford University Press, 1998), 20-22.

2. The Encyclopedia of Bioethics is in its third edition. See Stephen G. Post, ed., Encyclopedia of

Bioethics, vols. 1-5, 3rd ed. (New York: Macmillan Reference USA, 2004).

3. Several key bioethics journals include, but are not limited to, the American Journal of Bioethics, Journal of Clinical Ethics, Hastings Center Report, Bioethics, the Kennedy Institute of Ethics journal, and the National Catholic Bioethics Quarterly.

4. See Jonsen, Birth of Bioethics, and Jennifer K. Walter and Eran P. Klein, eds., The Story of Bioethics: From Seminal Works to Contemporary Explorations (Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press, 2003).

5. For example, the American Society for Bioethics and Humanities, the American Society of Law, Medicine, and Ethics, the Kennedy Institute of Ethics, and the Hastings Center.

6. See the compliance rules of the Department of Health and Human Services, Protection of Human Subjects, 45 CFR 46 (2005), §46.112.

7. See JACHO standards for accreditation: Joint Commission on Accreditation of Healthcare Organizations, Comprehensive Accreditation Manual for Hospitals (Oakbrook Terrace, IL: Joint Commission on Accreditation of Healthcare Organizations, 1999).

8. Though many dispute whether bioethics should be understood as a discipline in the narrow sense. See Jonsen, Birth of Bioethics, 325-51. See also Daniel Callahan, “Bioethics,” in Encyclopedia of Bioethics, 1:278-87; and idem, “Bioethics as a Discipline,” The Hastings Center Studies 1, no. 1 (1973): 66-73.

9. Callahan, “Bioethics,” 280. See also Warren T. Reich, “How Bioethics Got Its Name,” Hastings Center Report 23, no. 6 (November 1993): S6.

10. Samuel Gorovitz, “Bioethics and Social Responsibility,” The Monist 60 (January 1977): 3.

BIBLIOGRAPHY

Ashley, Benedict M., Kevin O’Rourke, and Jean K. deBlois. Health Care Ethics: A Catholic Theological Analysis. 5th ed. Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press, 2006.

Beauchamp, Tom L., and James E Childress. Principles of Biomedical Ethics. 5th ed. New York: Oxford University Press, 2001.

Beauchamp, Tom L., LeRoy Walters, Jeffrey P. Kahn, and Anna C. Mastroianni, eds. Contemporary Issues in Bioethics. 7th ed. Belmont, CA: Wadsworth, 2007.

Cahill, Lisa Sowle. Theological Bioethics: Participation, Justice, and Change. Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press, 2005.

Crigger, Bette-Jane, ed. Cases in Bioethics: Selections from the Hastings Center Report. 3rd ed. New York: St. Martin’s Press, 1998.

Department of Health and Human Services. Protection of Human Subjects. 45 CFR 46. 2005. §46.112.

Fletcher, Joseph. Morals and Medicine. Princeton, NJ: Beacon Press, 2000.

. Humanhood: Essays in Biomedical Ethics. Buffalo, NY: Prometheus Books, 1979.

Fletcher, Joseph F., and James F. Childress. Situation Ethics: The New Morality. Louisville, KY: Westminster John Knox Press, 1997.

Gorovitz, Samuel, et al., eds. Moral Problems in Medicine. 2nd ed. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice- Hall, 1983.

Harron, Frank, John Burnside, and Tom Beauchamp. Health and Human Values: A Guide to Making Your Own Decisions. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1983.

Joint Commission on Accreditation of Healthcare Organizations. Comprehensive Accreditation Manual for Hospitals. Oakbrook Terrace, IL: Joint Commission on Accreditation of Healthcare Organizations, 1999.

Jokobovits, Immanuel. Jewish Medical Ethics: A Comparative and Historical Study of the Jewish Religious Attitude of Medicine and Practice. New York: Bloch Publishing Company, 1997.

Jonsen, Albert R. The Birth of Bioethics. New York: Oxford University Press, 2003.

Jonsen, Albert R., Mark Siegler, and William J. Winslade. Clinical Ethics: A Practical Approach to Ethical Decisions in Clinical Medicine. 6th ed. New York: McGraw-Hill, 2006.

Jonsen, Albert R., Robert M. Veatch, and LeRoy Walters, eds. Sourcebook in Bioethics. Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press, 1998.

Kelly, David F. Contemporary Catholic Health Care Ethics. Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press, 2004.

Critical Care Ethics: Treatment Decisions in American Hospitals. Eugene, OR: Wipf and Stock, 2002.

The Emergence of Roman Catholic Medical Ethics in North America: An Historical-Methodological- Bibliographical Study. 2nd ed. New York: Edwin Mellen Press, 1979.

Kelly, Gerard. Medico-Moral Problems. St. Louis, MO: Catholic Hospital Association, 1958.

Kuczewski, Mark G., and Rosa Lynn B. Pinkus. An Ethics Casebook for Hospitals: Practical Approaches to Everyday Cases. Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press, 1999.

Levine, Carol, ed. Taking Sides: Clashing Views on Controversial Bioethical Issues. 12th ed. Guilford, Ontario: McGraw-Hill, 2007.

Mackler, Aaron. An Introduction to Catholic and Jewish Bioethics: A Comparative Analysis. Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press, 2003.

ed. Life and Death Responsibilities in Jewish Biomedical Ethics. New York: Louis Finkelstein Institute, 2000.

May, William E The Physician’s Covenant: Image of the Healer in Medical Ethics. 2nd ed. Louisville, KY: Westminster John Knox Press, 2007.

McCormick, Richard. How Brave a New World?: Dilemmas in Bioethics. Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press, 1981.

Menikoff, Jerry. Law and Bioethics: An Introduction. Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press, 2001.

Panicola, Michael R., John Paul Slosar, Mark E Repenshek, and David M. Belde. An Introduction to Health Care Ethics: Theological Foundations, Contemporary Issues, and Controversial Cases. Winona, MN: St. Mary’s Press, 2007.

Pence, Gregory E. Classic Cases in Medical Ethics: Accounts of the Cases That Shaped and Define Medical Ethics. 5th ed. New York: McGraw-Hill, 2007.

Classic Works in Medical Ethics: Core Philosophical Readings. Boston: McGraw-Hill, 1997.

Ramsey, Paul. The Patient as a Person: Explorations in Medical Ethics. 2nd ed. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 2002.

Ethics at the Edges of Life: Medical and Legal Intersections. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1978.

Reich, Warren, ed. The Encyclopedia of Bioethics. 2nd ed. New York: Macmillan, 1995.

Shannon, Thomas A., ed. Bioethics: Basic Writings on the Key Ethical Questions That Surround the Major, Modern Biological Possibilities and Problems. 4th ed. Mahwah, NJ: Paulist Press, 1993.

Shannon, Thomas A., and Joann Manfra, eds. Law and Bioethics: Texts with Commentary on Major Court Decisions. New York: Paulist Press, 1982.

Starr, Paul. The Social Transformation of American Medicine: The Rise of a Sovereign Profession and the Making of a Vast Industry. New York: Basic Books, 1982.

Veatch, Robert M. Case Studies in Medical Ethics. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1977.

Verhey, Allen, and Stephen Lammers, eds. On Moral Medicine: Theological Perspectives in Medical Ethics. 2nd ed. Grand Rapids, MI: William B. Eerdmans, 1998.

Walter, James J., and Thomas A. Shannon. Contemporary Issues in Bioethics: A Catholic

Perspective. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield, 2005.

Walter, Jennifer, and Eran Klein, eds. The Story of Bioethics: From Seminal Works to Contemporary Explorations. Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press, 2003.

INTRODUCTION

Humans have always seemed to find ways of intervening in nature. The ability to make a fire and the invention of the wheel had profound impacts on the development of human society. The domestication of plants and animals allowed humans to live in ways unthought of before. The rise of modern science and the Industrial Revolution stand as markers of yet another major change in our way of life.

Our current technological revolution presents further opportunities for intervening in life on both the micro and macro levels. The technologies surrounding conception and birth, such as in vitro fertilization and amniocentesis, help determine when we will be born and what some of our qualities may (or may not) be. Developments in genetics led to the production of new grains that produce more bushels per acre.’ An oil-eating bacterium has been manufactured to help clean up oil spills.’ Although a totally implantable artificial heart is not yet a reality, various assist devices are available to serve as a transition to technology; in fact, some researchers are developing technology that makes threedimensional tissues using inkjet technology.’ In terms of regenerative medicine, the hope for these scientists is to one day use the technology to create fully functional replacement organs or tissues. The sequencing of the human genome by the Human Genome Project and Celera Genomics has given us the map and sequence of our genetic structure. Current research is aimed at deciphering the functions of our genes for new approaches to treating genetic diseases and preventing others.

Technology touches virtually every part of our lives; but the moral record of technology is certainly a mixed one. Clearly technology has brought benefits. Computers have given us incredible capacities for calculating and information processing. The vast amounts of information about individuals collected and stored through technology raise serious issues of privacy and confidentiality. Medical technologies provide improved diagnostic capacities, but frequently we can do little or nothing about the disease diagnosed. Other technologies have fairly negative consequences. Nuclear weapons brought us to the brink of annihilation. To protect national interests, governments continue to develop more sophisticated instruments of “interrogation.” The impact of yet other technologies is mixed. Nuclear power stations provide necessary energy but problems of waste disposal have yet to be fully resolved. Birth technologies provide children but do not cure infertility. In addition, many wonder whether such technologies reduce children to commodities. Developments in biotechnology promise new cures or the end of global hunger, yet they carry threats to social justice, biodiversity, and ecological harmony.

Whatever one’s judgment about a particular technology, technology is here to stay and will continue to have far-reaching effects on our lives.

CHARACTERISTICS OF TECHNOLOGY

While specific technologies vary, technology itself has several common themes. Let us indicate some of these by following ideas proposed by Norman Faramelli in his book Technethics.4 Here, we will introduce six characteristic themes of technology.

The Empirical or Pragmatic Spirit

This is certainly close to the American spirit. We want to get the job done and get it done quickly. The issue is results, preferably results that we can measure.

Functionalism

Functionalism follows from the pragmatic bent of our culture. The issue is design and performance. We are frequently more concerned about how something will work than why we should do it.

Preoccupation with Means, Not Ends

We know that it is often easier to figure out how to solve a particular problem than to agree on which problem ought to be solved. The question of ends requires explicit value judgments for solutions. We often hope that we can finesse that difficult debate by focusing on the means-and by pretending that the means debate involves no value or ethical judgments.

Preference for Quantity over Quality

An old song says that if you can’t be with the one you love, then love the one you’re with. This attitude reflects-among other things-a preference for that which is at hand, for what is available, rather than that which is better. Of course, quantitative measurements are easier to do and the phrase the bottom line has a nice objective, realistic ring to it. Yet for all the material goods available to us, we seem too unsatisfied, unfulfilled. Plus, knowledge of the bottom line may not give us the important information we want and need for critical decision making.

Efficiency and Profit

The concept of standardization led to the development of interchangeable parts, which led to mass production, which led to fewer skilled laborers being needed, which led to lower wages, which led to higher profits. Now robots, which are directed by computers, perform much of this process-hence, the emergence of automation in manufacturing. Pragmatism, functionalism, and preoccupation with means and quantity all join here to promote efficiency in the service of higher profits.

Manipulation

Concern for efficiency and quantity leads to a desire to exercise greater rational control over all phases of life. For only in this way can one increase productivity at a cost-effective level.

Manipulation to achieve rational control is one thread in the manufacturing process-though the final word on the use of robots is yet to be heard. But such manipulation may be quite another thing if we begin more intensive selection of characteristics of our offspring through advanced diagnostic technologies and genetic interventions.

WHAT IS TECHNOLOGY?

Having seen some of the characteristics of technology, let’s now look to defining it. An obvious approach to technology is through hardware-the machines, the instruments, the robots. This is certainly an important part of technology, for this dimension of it clearly has a major impact on our lives.

Others, however, like French theologian Jacques Ellul see technology more as technique.’ Technique is a complex of standardized means for achieving a predetermined result. Someone using technology obtains results through a deliberate and rationalized process, using many of the characteristics of technology described above. Technique is the rational organization of behavior, not hardware or output; in other words, technique is like software.

This orientation is more helpful because it allows us to see technology as a cultural phenomenon, a method of organization, an angle of vision. While the products of the technological revolution impact our lives, technology as an organizational method for both thought and social interaction profoundly affects our social reality.

Daniel Bell has also analyzed technology and has defined five essential dimensions: function, energy, fabrication, communication and control, and regulated decision making.’

Function

Function is the primary element in design and relates to nature only insofar as nature is an efficient guide. As noted before, the issue is what something does and how something performs, not why we should do this.

Energy

The technological revolution gradually demanded new power sources, and we fulfilled that need by shifting from natural sources such as wind, water, and personal strength to manufactured sources such as steam and electricity. Now that we are depleting the natural resources required for their generation, we are turning to nuclear power. Our need for power is outstripping both our resources and our capacity to generate it, and this is creating a crisis, nationally and internationally.

Fabrication

Bell uses this word to describe the process of standardization of both parts and actions. This permits the replacement of one part or person with another so that one can achieve greater efficiency. One can use this process in manufacturing, in organizing a corporation, or in education.

Communication and Control

Technological systems feed off information and require increasing amounts of it to keep the system going. Thus, whoever controls the communication system controls the power. Information is useless unless someone communicates it, and technology, through increasing utilization of computer networks, provides an increasingly effective and efficient method of communication and control. Of course, this has vast implications for social power because not everyone will have access to these technologies or know how to use them.

Decision-Making Rules

Since function, fabrication, and communication are critical parts of the technological culture, we need to be assured that there will be coherence in their use and application. Rules of communication and decision making cannot be random or spontaneous, or the vital flow of information may be interrupted. Thus there is a need for speed and accuracy in the decision-making process, which calls for greater standardization, which leads to further decisions about what one will or will not include in decision making. This, of course, leads to a greater centralization of power and reinforces communication and control systems.

Whether understood as hardware or software, technology has profound effects on our everyday lives. Because of this, people see the need to examine technology to predict its effects and to evaluate them. Such assessments will, we hope, help us avoid many undesirable aspects or consequences of a particular technology.

One such method of evaluation is called technological assessment. This is a systematic study of the effects on society that may occur when a technology is introduced, expanded, or modified, with special emphasis on the impacts that are unintended, indirect, and delayed. This method attempts to evaluate a broad range of effects, including-but not limited to- environmental, social, economic, and political dimensions. Thus, a technological assessment seeks to examine as thoroughly as possible the short- and long-term consequences of a technology, its risks and benefits, its social and environmental impacts, and the cultural implications. Only by attending to all of these dimensions can one obtain a full sense of the significance of a technology.

Henk ten Have, a professor of medical ethics in the Netherlands, has argued that we must also recognize that technologies may “recast the initial problem into a new phraseology that may create new concepts; they also relocate problems and may shift responsibility for finding acceptable solutions.”‘ From this perspective an assessment of technology should not only examine the implications of introducing a new technology as noted above, but also examine the impact of technical rationality on ourselves, our personal and professional relations, and our society. This technical rationality has led to a preference for compartmentalization, a diminishment or even distrust of subjectivity, and a preference for instruments and objectivity. This orientation to technological assessment follows from understanding technology as a way of thinking. The important part of a technology assessment, then, is to think of how the introduction of a technology helps us reconceptualize or reimagine who we are as well as our relation to society.

TYPES OF TECHNOLOGY

In his study of technology, Daniel Callahan identified five types of technology.” The purpose of developing this classification schema was to help us see the potential of various technologies as well as understand the impact various technologies have on our lives. They are preservation technologies, improvement technologies, implementation technologies, destructive technologies, and compensatory technologies.

Preservation Technologies

These technologies help us adapt to nature or to survive various environments so we can fit into our environment, or help us investigate our environment. Some examples of these technologies are our homes, furnaces, irrigation systems, eyeglasses, and telescopes.

Improvement Technologies

Technologies such as these enable people to meet their felt needs or to go beyond the limits of their particular natural capabilities. As such, improvement technologies can enhance our physical dimensions or can help decorate or embellish our bodies. Examples of these are genetic engineering, prosthetics, and cosmetic surgery.

Implementation Technologies

These technologies are difficult to describe because their purpose is to assist in the implementation of other technologies. One can best think of these technologies as facilitators or enhancers. Thus, the computer allows us access to other information technologies, and the telephone allows us access to information. Planned obsolescence or the changing fashion allows people to have work.

Destructive Technologies

Technologies such as these are designed with one primary purpose: destruction. They may help us achieve other ends, but the purpose of these technologies is clear from their design. Such technologies may achieve their end through manipulation and control or simply by the capacity for obliteration. Examples are behavior modification technologies, weapon systems, and vacuum aspirators.

Compensatory Technologies

Having developed and implemented all manner of technologies, we now need other technologies to help us deal with the effects of these technologies on our lives. Thus, we have machines to help us exercise, we have noise-canceling headphones to help drown the sounds of other technologies, and we have sensitivity training to enable us to experience the world of nature that we have removed through technology.

UNDERSTANDINGS OF NATURE

Individuals or groups always use or apply technologies within a context. One critical context affected by our view of technology is that of nature. Here, we present three views of nature, developed by Daniel Callahan, to help understand both the arena in which technologies are often applied and some of the presuppositions we bring to them.

Nature as Plastic

In this perspective, one sees nature as alien and removed from human beings. It is outside of us and we are separate from it. It is plastic in that humans can shape and use it in any way human beings see fit. The model assumes that the only limit to nature is the limit human beings put on it. Thus, nature is totally at the disposal of human beings.

Nature as Sacred

This tradition finds a home in both Eastern and Western religious traditions. Taoism suggests conformity to nature so that an individual may become part of the cosmic whole of which nature is a manifestation. The medieval theologian Bonaventure, following the lead of Francis of Assisi, saw nature as the footprints of God. The natural was a reflection of the glory of God. These perspectives create an attitude of stewardship or conservation of nature. While one may intervene, such acts should be discrete, infrequent, and reverent.

Nature as Teleological

This understanding of nature suggests that there is a purpose and logic in nature. There is an inner dynamism that leads nature to certain ends. There is a limit that prevents the violation of nature. Thus, the extent of interventions into nature is set by the dynamism of nature itself.

What we think we can do determines, in part, what we do. If, for example, we think that nature is only an object existing apart from us, we may be willing to consider more interventions than if we thought of it as being part of an organic whole that is sensitive to interventions.

Ironically, the Judeo-Christian tradition is partly responsible for the desacralization of nature. In its clear and firm rejection of idolatry and its affirmation of God’s being a God of nature rather than a God in nature, that tradition helped validate the objectification of nature. While many in that tradition would not want to intervene to the same extent that others have, nonetheless the balance is a difficult one to maintain.

RESPONSIBILITIES OF SCIENTISTS

In addition to thinking about the various meanings of technology and nature, we also need to think of the responsibilities of the scientists, for these are the individuals most directly involved in interventions into nature. James Gustafson proposed four models we can use to think about professional responsibility in this area and to evaluate the consequences of a particular position.’

Total Intervention

In this position, scientists would have the right to do whatever is possible; some call this the technological imperative. The justification for this position is the inherent value of knowledge itself. This is complemented by the valuing of intellectual curiosity and the seemingly inherent human drive to solve problems. In this model the only limit is the lack of technical capacity.

No Intervention

This blanket prohibition is based on either a view of nature as sacred and therefore inviolable or a conviction that the proposed research violates a limit imposed by nature. This model is reminiscent of the position of some Native Americans who refused to practice agriculture because to do so was to rip up the breast of their mother, the earth. Total consistency in this position would lead to the reduction of the human community to huntingand-gathering societies. Thus, many individuals would not use this principle absolutely but would rather understand it as a strong check on the previous understanding of intervention.

Limited Interventions

This perspective argues that scientists have no right to change the most distinctive human characteristics. This model, related to an understanding of nature as teleological, sees interventions checked by a particular limit: human nature. Thus, one can intervene in nature (as opposed to the second model) but human nature is the boundary, not lack of technical capacity (as in the first model).

Directed Interventions

This model says that scientists have the right to foster the growth of valued human characteristics and to remove those that are harmful. This model suggests a high level of intervention both to control and to direct human development. The goal is quality of life, and it is served by directing human growth and removing obstacles to its fulfillment.

Clearly, nobody practices these models in a pure form, but we do find traces of them in most of us. The issue is to use these perspectives to understand better why we are intervening in nature and to ask if there are any restraints on this. In other words, one can use these models as a way to evaluate a scientist’s responsibility in the development and use of technology.

SOCIETY, SCIENCE, AND TECHNOLOGY

For those who are not bench scientists, a helpful way to think about being responsible with technology is to consider the relationships between society, science, and technology. Ian Barbour illustrates three ways to understand technology: technology as threat, technology as liberator, and technology as an instrument of power.’° Barbour argues that technology should be seen as an instrument of power, formed by dynamic interactions between society, science, and technology itself. Because institutions yield these instruments and exercise their powers, technology serves institutional interests, which include human values (e.g., goods necessary for human beings to flourish), expansion of human knowledge (a value itself), profit, and so on. These interests interact and help shape the research, development, marketing, and use of technology across a wide array of human situations. It is within these situations that individuals and groups face the profound bioethical questions in the responsible use of these technologies.

SUMMARY

If we look around us, it is clear that technology is here to stay. Our culture is utterly dependent on

various aspects of it. We could not get through our day without technology. From clocks to microwaves to transportation systems to digital video recorders and high-definition TV, our lives, work, and entertainment are inherently tied up with technology.

Our quality of life has greatly increased because of technology. We live in greater comfort in various climates. We have abundant food and water supplies, we can communicate and travel much more efficiently, and our health has improved.

After two world wars and attacks such as the one on September 11, 2001, we have become acutely aware of how some can use technology to cause terror and suffering throughout the world. We stand in daily dread of the release of weapons that could destroy us-whether they are designed for destruction (e.g., nuclear weapons) or not (e.g., commercial aircraft). We have more information accessible to us but we know less of what it means or what to do with it. Pollution, a byproduct of our technical culture, is threatening to destroy our ecosystem. Many resources needed for daily living are in short supply or in danger of being depleted.

Thus many benefits and problems are given to us by technology. Each requires much study and examination. But it is to one

DISCUSSION QUESTIONS

1. What are the costs and benefits, the strengths and weaknesses, of the vast technological society that has developed in America?

2. What are some examples of unintended and delayed side effects of technology? Do you think these could have been avoided?

3. Develop lists of examples of the various types of technologies. What needs are these technologies meant to satisfy? What values are these technologies based on?

4. How has technology benefited your life? How has it complicated your life?

5. Which is more helpful for you: to think of technology as hardware or as a system? Why?

NOTES

1. David Zilberman, Holly Ameden, and Matin Qaim, “The Impact of Agricultural Biotechnology on Yields, Risks, and Biodiversity in Low-Income Countries,” Journal of Developmental Studies 43 (2007): 63-78.

2. Victor de Lorenzo, “Blueprint of an Oil-Eating Bacterium,” Nature Biotechnology 24 (2006): 952-53.

3. Tao Xu, Joyce Jin, Cassie Gregory, James J. Hickman, and Thomas Boland, “Inkjet Printing of Viable Mammalian Cells,” Biomaterials 26 (2005): 93-99.

4. Norman J. Faramelli, Technethics (New York: Friendship Press, 1971), 31 ff.

5. Jacques Ellul, The Technological Society (New York: Vintage Books, 1964), 13ff.

6. Daniel Bell, faculty seminar presentation (Worchester Polytechnic Institute, 1976); see also idem, The Coming of the PostIndustrial Society: A Venture in Social Forecasting (New York: Basic Books, 1973).

7. Henk A. M. J. ten Have, “Medical Technology Assessment and Ethics: Ambivalent Relations,” Hastings Center Report 25 (September-October 1995): 18.

8. Daniel Callahan, The Tyranny of Survival (New York: Macmillan, 1973), 55ff.

9. James Gustafson, “Basic Issues in the Biomedical Fields,” Soundings 53 (Summer 1970): 151ff.

10. Ian G. Barbour, Ethics in an Age of Technology: The Gifford Lectures 1989-1991, vol. 2 (New York: HarperCollins Publishers, 1993), 3-25.

BIBLIOGRAPHY

Barbour, Ian. Ethics in an Age of Technology: The Gifford Lectures 1989-1991. Volume 2. New York: HarperCollins Publishers, 1993.

ed. Science and Religion. San Francisco: Harper and Row, 1968.

Bell, Daniel. The Coming of the Post-Industrial Society: A Venture in Social Forecasting. New York: Basic Books, 1973.

Bronowsky, Joseph. Science and Human Values. San Francisco: Harper and Row, 1965.

Bross, I. D. J. “Metatechnology: A Technology for the Safe, Effective, and Economical Use of Technology.” Theoretical Medicine 2 (1981): 145-53.

Callahan, Daniel. The Tyranny of Survival. New York: Macmillan, 1973.

de Lorenzo, Victor. “Blueprint of an Oil-Eating Bacterium.” Nature Biotechnology 24 (2006): 952- 53.

Diamond, Jared. Guns, Germs, and Steel. New York: W. W. Norton & Co., 2005.

Ehrlich, Paul R. Human Natures. Washington, DC: Island Press, 2000.

Ellul, Jacques. The Technological Society. New York: Vintage Books, 1964.

Faramelli, Norman J. Technethics. New York: Friendship Press, 1971.

Ferkiss, Victor C. The Future of Technological Civilization: The Myth and the Reality. New York: George Braziller, 1969.

Gustafson, James. “Basic Issues in the Biomedical Fields.” Soundings 53 (Summer 1970): 151-80.

Hardin, Garrett. Exploring New Ethics for Survival: The Voyage of Spaceship Beagle. New York: Viking Press, 1972.

Haring, Bernhard. Ethics of Manipulation: Issues in Medicine, Behavior Control, and Genetics. New York: Seabury Press, 1975.

Have, Henk A. M. J. ten. “Medical Technology Assessment and Ethics: Ambivalent Relations.” The Hastings Center Report 25 (September-October 1995): 13-19.

Kuhn, Thomas. The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1970.

Lappe, Marc. Genetic Politics: The Limits of Biological Control. New York: Simon and Schuster, 1977.

Lock, Margaret, and Deborah Gordon. Biomedicine Reconsidered. Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1988.

MacKay, Donald. Human Science and Human Dignity. Downers Grove, IL: Intervarsity Press, 1979.

Shinn, Roger. Forced Options: Social Decisions for the 21st Century. San Francisco: Harper and Row, 1982.

Shinn, Roger, and Paul Abrecht, eds. Faith and Science in an Unjust World: Report of the World Council of Churches’ Conference on Faith, Science, and the Future. 2 vols. Geneva: World Council of Churches, 1981.

Xu, Tao, Joyce Jin, Cassie Gregory, James J. Hickman, and Thomas Boland. “Inkjet Printing of Viable Mammalian Cells.” Biomaterials 26 (2005): 93-99.

Zilberman, David, Holly Ameden, and Matin Qaim. “The Impact of Agricultural Biotechnology on Yields, Risks, and Biodiversity in Low-Income Countries.” Journal of Developmental Studies 43 (2007): 63-78.

INTRODUCTION

In the last chapter, we saw the importance of responsibility in the research, development, and use of technology, including biomedical technology. In this chapter, we will explore ways we can judge which uses of technology, or our moral choices, are the most responsible. This examination of the criteria upon which one bases such decisions is called ethical analysis. Our principal goal is to prepare you for some of the discussions that will emerge in the various topics we will cover and to suggest basic frameworks for ethical analysis.

ETHICAL ISSUES

What are ethical issues? One can think of ethical issues as the variables one considers in making a judgment or decision about which option is the best or more morally viable. Ethical issues can constitute a range of areas in the moral life-from the macro-level issues in public policy to the micro- level issues of end-of-life treatment decisions at a patient’s bedside. We cannot, however, address ethical issues in a vacuum; we need an overarching framework or structure to analyze them properly. Thus, to answer the question, How do we make ethical judgments or responsible decisions? we apply ethical theories, which are informed by the various ethical issues at stake.

ETHICAL THEORIES

In general, an ethical theory is the process by which we justify a particular decision or answer a specific normative question; a theory provides an overarching framework in which one addresses and evaluates ethical issues. Ethical theories organize complex information and competing values and interests, and help us formulate answers to questions such as What should I do? What kind of person should I be? or What is the right course of action? The main purpose of a theory is to provide consistency and coherence in our decision making. That is, an ethical theory gives us a common approach to various problems. If we have a theory, we do not have to figure out where to begin each time we meet a new problem. A theory also allows us to develop some degree of consistency in our decision making; we aim at reliable patterns of practical reason, not whimsical emotional or uncritical reactions. We will begin to see how different values relate to one another. If we are consistent and coherent in our decision making, we will have a greater degree of internal unity and integrity in our decision making. Given the complexity of problems in bioethics, these qualities are extremely worthwhile.

One can organize different kinds of ethical theories in two categories: action-based theories and character-based theories. There are two very basic sets of moral questions one can ask.’ The first

kind of questions has to do with human behavior in action: an ethics of doing. The second kind of questions has to do with being human itself: an ethics of being. Generally speaking, all ethical theories address aspects of the moral life: what it is, how to live it, and so on. Action-based ethical theories are basically oriented to answering ethical questions of the first kind-ethics of doing. They attempt to figure out what is the right or good thing to do. We already discussed two kinds of action- based theories (deontology and teleology) in chapter 1. Character-based ethical theories, in the broadest sense of the term, are basically oriented to answering ethical questions of the second kind- ethics of being. They attempt to figure out who a good person is and what such a person ought to do.

Our goal in this section is to introduce the basic structures of various ethical theories and briefly sketch some advantages and disadvantages of each. Unfortunately, we cannot provide a thorough examination of ethical theories that many moral philosophers have proffered. Instead, we have provided a list of works in the bibliography regarding moral philosophy and theology of ethical theory. Thus, this section is not exhaustive of (a) the variety of ethical theories or (b) the analyses of them.

Action-Based Ethical Theories

Action-based ethical theories address moral questions pertaining to human behavior in action. In this regard, an ethics of doing can move in two directions: an evaluation of the means (the act, process, or way a human behaves) or an evaluation of the ends (the ends, outcomes, or consequences of the particular human behavior). On the one hand, we saw in chapter 1 that teleological ethical theories, like consequentialism, assess the values, goods, benefits, or utility in relation to the disvalues, evils, harms, or burdens in the results of a human action. Deontological ethical theories, on the other hand, assess the action itself by reference to particular rules, duties, or norms, which ask primarily whether the means constitute or violate such duties.

Teleological Ethics. An action-based ethical theory, like consequentialism, answers the question, What should I do? by considering the consequences of various options in a decision. That is, what is ethical is the option that brings about consequences that have the greatest number of advantages over disadvantages or that generate the greatest good for the greatest number of people. Basically, in this theory, one determines what is moral by looking to outcomes, to consequences, and to the situation.

The ethical theories of situation ethics and utilitarianism are common types of action-based, consequentialist ethical theories. We discussed situation ethics in but another common consequentialist theory is utilitarianism, which Jeremy Bentham and John Stuart Mill developed.’ Utilitarianism states that what is moral maximizes “utility” in the consequences of an act-for example, the greatest good for the greatest number of people. A principle of utility specifies what constitutes “utility” or what is “useful.” A consequence (or set of consequences) may have utility if (on balance) it evokes happiness, including, pleasure, health, knowledge, and so forth.

The major benefit of this kind of theory is that it looks to the actual impact of a particular decision and asks how such a decision will affect people. Consequentialism is attuned to the nuances of life and seeks to be responsive to them. The major problem of this theory is that the theory itself provides no standard by which one could measure one outcome against another. That is, while being sensitive to the circumstances, consequentialism has no basis for evaluating the relative merits or problems of

one outcome against another.

Deontological Ethics. Deontological ethics looks to one’s obligations to determine what is moral. This theory answers the question What should I do? by specifying one’s obligations or moral duties. That is, the moral act is one in which one meets his or her obligations, his or her responsibilities, or fulfills his or her duties. For a deontologist, obligations and rules are primary, for only by attending to these dimensions of morality can one be sure that self-interest does not override moral obligations. The Ten Commandments, Kant’s Categorical Imperative,’ and certain forms of rights ethics are probably the most common examples of deontological ethics.

Rights ethics is a theory that resolves moral dilemmas by first determining what rights or moral claims are involved. Then one settles dilemmas in terms of a hierarchy of rights. Paramount for a person of this orientation is that the moral claims of individualstheir rights-are taken seriously. Rights may include duties, privileges, or entitlements. The duties relative to certain rights may be the duty of the subject (e.g., the right to vote implies a duty and a privilege to vote) or a duty on others (e.g., the right to privacy suggests a duty not to invade another’s privacy). The ethical theory of rights is a popular one in our American culture. Consider, for example, the central role this theory plays in abortion and health care access debates.

On the one hand, the main advantage of a rights theory is that it highlights the moral centrality of the person and his or her moral claims in a situation of ethical conflict. On the other hand, this theory does not tell us how to resolve conflicts of rights between individuals. The theory makes the claims of the individual central without telling us how to resolve potential conflicts of rights.

The major benefit of deontological ethics is the clarity and certainty of its starting point. Once the rules are known, the duties determined, or the rights identified, then what is ethical is evident. The major problem is the potential insensitivity to circumstances and consequences. By looking only at duty or rights, one may miss important aspects of a problem.

Character-Based Ethical Theories

Character-based ethical theories address moral questions dealing with who good persons are and how they ought to relate to one another. In these ways, an ethics of being deals with character traits (e.g., virtues and vices) as well as human relationships. Many philosophers have critiqued character- based ethics for being too subjective or relative to individuals or their particular communities. With feminism and the work of scholars such as Edmund Pellegrino and David Thomasma, Alasdair Maclntyre, Carol Gilligan, and others, however, ethics of being has seen a revival in recent years. We will consider briefly three kinds of character-based ethics here.

Virtue Ethics. Virtue ethics comes from a long line of philosophers and theologians dating at least all the way back to Ancient Greece. For example, Aristotle developed a virtue-based theory of ethics,’ and Thomas Aquinas built upon Aristotle’s work for Christianity. More recently, Alasdair Maclntyre revitalizes this approach to ethics; Edmund Pellegrino and David Thomasma apply it to the practice of medicine.’ James Keenan asks what virtue ethics can bring to discussions of the new genetics.` In its basic form, virtue ethics is about making a habit of good behavior; that is, making good behavior a part of who we are. A virtue, or a vice, is a character trait that describes one’s

orientation to certain goods and the behaviors that seek those goods. Like all characterbased theories, virtue ethics sees an intimate relationship between what we do and who we are. Thus, the virtue- related questions include, What would a virtuous physician do when faced with physician-assisted suicide? What (or who) is a virtuous physician? What does it mean to be a virtuous parent? By wanting to become a virtuous parent, should I use assisted reproductive technology or adopt?

Bioethics

 
"Looking for a Similar Assignment? Get Expert Help at an Amazing Discount!"

BIOL134 Experiment Design Plan

BIOL134 Experiment Design Plan. Experimental Design Plan

For your course project you are tasked with designing and carrying out a research project on plant transpiration of your own design using the Vernier instruments (see Transpiration Lab Student Guide for directions). Transpiration is the process by which moisture moves through a plant.  The process is broken down and explained in chapter 30, section 30.5 of the text book. The purpose of this assignment is to help you plan and design an experiment investigating the factors that impact plant transpiration. After this assignment is complete you will be able to conduct your experiment, collect data and prepare for the experiment analysis. During week 15 you will submit an experiment report using information from your design plan and experiment results. Please note that experiments that do not use the Vernier sensors will receive a grade of 0 so make sure you have your sensors ordered and available by week 15 when you must turn in your experiment report.

The Experimental Design Plan assignment is Due Week 6. Submit the attached experiment design sheet with answers as an attachment.

Instructions:

Look through the directions in the transpiration lab student guides. Before performing an experiment or lab, you must design and plan what is going to be tested and how you are going to test it. You must be organized and be able to communicate your results effectively.  This assignment is designed to help you organize your experiment design. Use what you have learned about the scientific method from your lab assignments to help you design an experiment on plant transpiration. You will need to conduct some background research on plant transpiration to help you design your experiment. The research will be used to help you write the introduction portion of your experiment paper.

An experiment is a research method in which you manipulate a variable or variables under very controlled conditions and examines whether any changes occur in response to the manipulation of the variable.

It is a cause and effect relationship

1. Experiment introduction & background research with references in APA format (50 pts)

Before you can design an experiment, you need to have a good understanding of the current research. You need to summarize what research is currently known about your experiment question in the introduction of your report. This part of the assignment allows you to get a jump start on that task while building valuable knowledge that will help you in your experiment design.

1) Visit the APUS library and internet to research information on plant transpiration. The program guide for natural sciences is a good starting place to begin your APUS library research: https://apus.libguides.com/natural_sciences 

2) Look through these examples of how to share background research in an introduction: https://unilearning.uow.edu.au/report/2biii1.html

Collect background information for your research experiment and use references and in text citations to back up you research. Explain any ideas or techniques that are necessary for someone to understand your experiment. At the minimum you should cover what transpiration is, what role/influence your independent variable has on enzymes, why this is important, your testable question and hypothesis. The introduction is generally 1 page long. You need to use APA formatted in text citations and references and this should be written in the 3rd person. You need to use at least 4 different academic references for your background research.

The grading in this section of the assignment is broken down as follows:

Coverage of topic including scientific question and hypothesis: 30 points

4 academic references and APA reference and citation technique: 15 points

Grammar/spelling/voice:5 points

Need tips on APA in text citations? They can be found here: https://owl.english.purdue.edu/owl/resource/560/02/

Need tips on APA reference formatting? They can be found here: https://owl.english.purdue.edu/owl/resource/560/05/

Want a handy tool that formats your references in APA for you? Visit this website: http://www.calvin.edu/library/knightcite/index.php

 

2. Identify the Independent Variable, Dependent Variable and Constants (10pts)

· Independent Variable is the variable that is manipulated. It is the variable that you change on purpose. (The CAUSE) There are many variables that can change transpiration. You will choose only 1 independent variable to test. You can choose from temperature, light, humidity, plant species, or air flow.

· Dependent Variable is the variable that we measure in response to the manipulation of the independent variable. It is a measurable change. State what are we measuring to gauge transpiration in our experiment here(The EFFECT)

· Constants are all the other variables in the experiment that must remain the same so we can see what effect the independent variable has on the dependent variable.

· The Control is used as a standard of comparison. The control is a level of the independent variable that has been changed the least or not at all.

 

 

 

3. Write a Title (5pts)

· Use the following pattern when writing a title…

The Effect of the (Independent Variable) on the (Dependent Variable)

 

4. Write a Testable Question (5pts)

Not all questions are testable!!

A testable question asks. . .

“What is the effect of the Independent Variable on the Dependent Variable?”

5. Write a Hypothesis (5pts)

A hypothesis is a prediction of the outcome of the lab. Your prediction is based on your understanding of the scientific concept.

It answers your testable question. Use the following pattern:

 

IF the (IV- how it is changing), then the DV- how you think it will change), BECAUSE (why do you think this is happening.

Example- If the IV increases, then the DV will decrease because….

6. Write your Procedures (20pts)

Procedures are a list of materials used in the experiment and the steps in performing the experimental part. Procedures are the recipe you follow in order to perform the experiment. Write these in order, in paragraph form, and using your own words. Do not simply copy and paste from the student lab guide.

7. Create your Data Table (5pts)

Data is recorded during the procedures. You need to create your data collection table for your experiment. Below is an example Data collection table. Create your own collection table using labels with the names of your variables and the correct units you are measuring. Do not collect data yet! You are just setting up the table so you are ready to collect data when it is time to run your experiment. Wait until you get feedback from this assignment to begin any data collection

·

{Insert name of Independent Variable} (insert units) {Insert name of Dependent Variable} (insert units)

 

Average { Insert name of Dependent Variable }(insert units)
  Trial 1 * Trial 2 * Trial 3*  
Control        
{Insert Treatment 1 Name}        
{Insert Treatment 2 Name}        
{Insert Treatment 3 Name}        

 

*Repeated Trials——Why repeat the experiment more than once?

Mistakes happen no matter how careful you are so if you repeat the experiment you will get more reliable data. The more repeated trials the more likely you will reduce the effect of chance errors and the more reliable your data becomes and the more confidence you can place in your data. Generally, a minimum of 3 trials is acceptable for experiments with more being better.

This is a great video that walks you through the setup steps involved in conducting the experiment:

https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=-hrMTHwiTPI

Read through the attached documents to understand how you will customize the experiment and make it your own.

~Adapted from the Hudsonville Area School District Experiment Design Cheat Sheet

BIOL134 Experiment Design Plan

 
"Looking for a Similar Assignment? Get Expert Help at an Amazing Discount!"

Medical Coding MCQ (25 Question)

Medical Coding MCQ (25 Question). Medical Coding 25 MCQ

1). A patient is admitted to undergo chemotherapy for cancer of the sigmoid colon that was previously treated with resection. Which code is sequenced first?

A. 153.3 B.153.9 C. V58.11 D. V10

2). A patient was admitted to the hospital for chest pain due to tachycardia. While in the hospital, the patient was also treated or type 1 diabetes. Upon further review, the coder noted that the documentation and EKG didn’t provide further evidence of the type of tachycardia or underlying cardiac condition(s).What should the coder report as the principal diagnosis?

A.Chest pain B.Tachycardia, NOS C.Insulin-dependent diabetes mellitus D.Cardiac disease, NOS

3). Dr. Smith recorded the following diagnoses on the patient’s discharge sheet: gastrointestinal bleeding due to acute gastritis and angiodysplasia. The principal diagnosis is coded as

A.GI bleeding. B.acute gastritis. C.angiodysplasia. D.either acute gastritis or angiodysplasia.

4. A patient was admitted with extreme fatigue and lethargy. Upon discharge, the physician documents: fatigue due to either depression or hypothyroidism. Which of the following are correct codes and sequencing for the scenario?

A. 780.79, 311, 244.9 B. 311, 249.9, 789.79 C. 249.9, 311 D. 789.79

5. Of the following, which code would take precedence over the other?

A. 072.0 over 033.0 B. 595.0 over 131.09 C. 486 over 480 D. 112.2 over 599.0

6. Upon discharge, the physician documents the following on the patient’s discharge sheet:?HIV infection. As the inpatient coder, your next step should be to

A. code the HIV infection as if it exists (according to UHDDS guidelines) and report it as the principal diagnosis.

B. review the UHDDS guidelines for assigning possible HIV infection codes versus AIDS codes.

C. query the physician and request that the statement be amended with a positive

(or negative) confirmation of the HIV infection.

D. wait to code the patient’s record until a positive finding on the serology report

confirms the HIV diagnosis.

7. For which of the following scenarios would it be appropriate to query the physician for more information before coding and/or sequencing?

A. A patient was admitted with severe abdominal pain. At discharge, the physician documents: abdominal pain due to either hiatal hernia or diverticula.

B. A patient was admitted with congestive heart failure (treated with IV furosemide) and unstable angina (treated with nitrates).

C. A patient has low potassium levels noted on the laboratory report (treated with orally administered potassium).

D. A patient is admitted with dysuria with no cause found.

8. Which of the following statements is true?

A. A patient has diabetes and an ulcer. Code the ulcer as diabetic.

B. A pregnant patient has diabetes. Code diabetes as complicating the pregnancy.

C. A patient has diabetes and cardiomyopathy. Code the cardiomyopathy as a diabetic complication.

D. A patient has diabetes and cataracts. Code diabetic cataracts.

9. A patient was admitted for metastatic carcinoma from the breast to several lymph node sites. Two years ago she had a double mastectomy. Which of the following is the correct code assignment for this case?

A. 196.8, V10.3 C. 196.8, 174.9, 85.42

B. 174.9, 196.8 D. 196.8, 174.9, V10.3

10. One of the secondary diagnoses listed on the patient’s discharge sheet is seizures. As a coder, your next step is probably

A. coding seizures to 780.39. B. coding seizures to 345.

C. not reporting the code because it’s a symptom.

D. querying the physician for more information/clarification.

11. A patient was discharged with the diagnosis of acute bronchitis with chronic obstructive asthma. Which of the following is the correctcoding and sequencing (if applicable) for this patient?

A.493.21 B. 493.21, 496 C. 466.0, 493.21 D. 493.91

12. Code 780.2 can be listed as principal diagnosis in which of the following cases?

A.For an outpatient encounter when the cause has been determined

B.For an inpatient encounter when the cause hasn’t been determined

C.When it’s listed with a contrasting diagnosis

D.It can never be listed as principal diagnosis.

13. Which of the following codes should not be listed as principal diagnosis?

A. 784.7 B.V30.00 C. E812.0 D. 307.81

14. Choose the correct code and sequencing for the following scenario: Reduction of right humerus fracture with cast.

A. 79.00 B.79.01 C. 79.00, 93.53 D. 79.01, 93.53

15. Read the following excerpt from medical record documentation and determine the correct code(s) for coding. The physician writes: “…noted burn on the arm skin with redness. Patient complained of tenderness to the touch.”

A. 943.01 B. 943.10 C. 943.21 D. 943.30

16. A patient was admitted in a coma from intentionally ingesting an entire bottle of sedatives. Which of the following is the correct coding and sequencing assignment?

A.780.01, 967.8 B. 780.01, 967.8, E950.2 C. 967.8, E950.2 D. 967.8, 780.01, E950.2

17. Which of the following situations would allow the assigning of a V code for a principal diagnosis?

A. Mother admitted for birth of infant, no complications

B. Patient admitted for dialysis

C. Patient admitted for metastatic breast cancer with a history of ovarian cancer

D. Patient admitted for poisoning has a history of alcoholism

18. A patient was admitted for nausea and vomiting due to gastroenteritis. Which of the following is thecorrect code reporting and sequencing?

A. 787.01, 787.02, 558.9 C. 558.9, 787.01

B. 787.02, 787.03, 558.9 D. 558.9

19. A physician lists positive findings on a purified protein derivative (PPD) test as a secondary diagnosis on the patient’s discharge sheet. How should this listing be coded?

A. 795.51 B. 010.95 C. 011.05 D. This listing shouldn’t be coded.

20. A physician lists urosepsis as a secondary diagnosis on a patient’s discharge sheet. How would you code this diagnosis?

A. Code it to 790.7. C. Code it to 599.0.

B. Code it to 038.9. D. Code 599.0, 038.9.

21. A patient is admitted for metastatic adenocarcinoma of the sacrum from the prostate. A prostatectomy was performed 11 months ago. Which of the following should be reported as the principal diagnosis for this patient?

A. V10 B. 185 C. 198.5 D. 170.6

22. A patient was discharged with a diagnosis of diabetes with nephropathy and chronic renal failure. How many codes would be reported for this patient?

A. One B. Two C. Three D. Need more information on the type of diabetes

23. If the physician describes the patient as presently in a manic phase, but has experienced depression in the past, this condition may be coded as

A. 296.4X B. 296.5X C. 296.6X D. Need more information

24. Codes 331.9, 332.0, are conditions affecting the

A. central nervous system. C. gastrointestinal system.

B. peripheral nervous system. D. cardiovascular system.

25. A patient was admitted with an acute exacerbation of chronic obstructive bronchitis and found to be in respiratory failure. Which of the following is the correct coding and sequencing for this case?

A. 518.81, 491.21 B. 491.21, 518.81 C. 518.81, 496 D. 493.91, 496, 518.81

U Can Also Purchase Other assignment for this Course ( Just Click On Below Link )

Medical Coding Level I (10 MCQ)

http://www.homeworkmarket.com/content/medical-coding-level-i-medical-coding-level-i

Medical Coding Level II

http://www.homeworkmarket.com/content/medical-coding-level-ii

Medical coding and Billing

http://www.homeworkmarket.com/content/medical-coding-and-billing-medical-coding-and-billing-mcq

Medical Coding Quiz 10 MCQ

http://www.homeworkmarket.com/content/medical-coding-quiz-10-mcq-medical-coding-quiz-10-mcq

Medical Coding MCQ (25 Question)

 
"Looking for a Similar Assignment? Get Expert Help at an Amazing Discount!"

Biology Lab Gene Expression

Biology Lab Gene Expression. To delve a bit deeper into our topic this week, we are going to spend some time using Phet’s Gene Expression Simulation, as well as work through the effects of various mutations on gene expression.  To access the simulation, you can either click on the Gene Expression Simulation Link below (recommended) or use the version that is embedded in each of the parts below.

HERE IS THE LINK TO THE  Gene Expression Simulation (Links to an external site.)

https://phet.colorado.edu/sims/html/gene-expression-essentials/latest/gene-expression-essentials_en.html

Gene Expression Lab Simulation worksheet adapted by L. McPheron & Shannon Nixon; Phet Simulation by Elizabeth Hobbs; Mutation worksheet by Eliza Woo

Objectives:

â—Ź Identify the roles transcription factors, RNA polymerase, ribosomes, and mRNA destroyers have on transcription and translation.

â—Ź Distinguish between the location and function of regulatory regions compared to transcribed regions of DNA.

â—Ź Predict the effects of concentration, affinity, and degradation rates of transcription factors and RNA polymerase on gene expression.

● Identify the effects of mutations on gene expression. Background: Transcription​ is the process of making mRNA from DNA. This is a highly regulated process that our cells complete in preparation to make a protein. ​Translation​ is the process of making a protein from a piece of mRNA.

DNA ——————–> mRNA ——————–> protein transcription translation

Not all regions of DNA are used to make mRNA – only the parts of DNA that correspond to genes. Even then, not all gene regions are transcribed all the time. When genes are transcribed into mRNA depends on the needs of the cell. Once mRNA is made from DNA, it is translated into protein. Translation is an energy expensive process (it requires LOTS of ATP) which is one reason the cell only completes the process when the protein product is needed. This week’s “Reading and Lesson” explains many of the details of these highly complicated processes, transcription and translation. Please review the lesson for a deeper understanding of the concepts in this lab activity. Procedure: Click the Play arrow on this ​Gene Expression activity​ to complete the simulations. (The simulations are also embedded in the Canvas lab assignment page.) You will complete 3 simulations: 1) Expression, 2) mRNA, and 3) Multiple Cells.

Part 1: Expression Simulation

Click “Expression” to start that simulation. Notice the molecule that spans across the screen, from left to right. Answer the following 2 questions:

1. What is this molecule that spans across the page that is shown in red and blue?

2. What do you think the different colors (red and blue) of the molecule represent?

 

1

 

 

 

Now, start the process of transcription.

For transcription, you need these things to happen. First, most genes require 1 or 2 “transcription factors” to bind to the area in front of the gene (called the “regulatory region”). Second, an RNA polymerase (an enzyme that makes mRNA from DNA) needs to be present in order for transcription to occur.

1. Drag one Positive Transcription Factor and one RNA Polymerase from the box called Biomolecule Toolbox to the regulatory region on the DNA molecule. This should start TRANSCRIPTION.

2. Now, drag a ribosome next to the mRNA, in order to do TRANSLATION. 3. The mRNA is eventually broken down by an mRNA destroyer protein. Drag one of these next to the

mRNA when it is done making a protein. 4. Put the protein in Your Protein Collection. 5. Stop the gene from working by dragging the Negative Transcription Factor to the Regulatory Area, and

remove the Positive Transcription Factor by dragging it out of the way.

After you have made 1 protein, answer these 5 questions. HINT: Think about what/where things are at the start, and what/ where things are at the end of the process.

1. What does the “Positive Transcription Factor” do?

 

 

2. What does the “RNA Polymerase” do?

 

3. What does the “Ribosome” do?

 

4. What does the “mRNA destroyer” do?

 

5. What does the “negative transcription” factor do?

 

2

 

 

 

Click the yellow “Next Gene” box to begin working on the second gene. Can you remember the steps in order from your first trial? Try to see if you can! (HINT: There is one small difference between the transcription of gene 2 versus gene 1 – the difference is not in the order of steps but in the amount of something!) If not, not to worry, we are still learning… As a reminder, the steps are:

1. Drag Positive Transcription Factors and one RNA Polymerase from the box called Biomolecule Toolbox to the regulatory region on the DNA molecule. This should start TRANSCRIPTION!

2. Now, drag a ribosome next to the mRNA, in order to do TRANSLATION! 3. The mRNA is eventually broken down by an mRNA destroyer protein. Drag one of these next to the

mRNA when it is done making a protein. 4. Put the protein in Your Protein Collection. 5. Stop the gene from working by dragging the Negative Transcription Factor to the Regulatory Area, and

remove the Positive Transcription Factors by dragging them out of the way.

After you have made the second protein, answer these 2 questions.

1. What is one difference you noticed that was required to initiate the transcription of gene 2 versus gene 1?

2. What could be an advantage of multiple positive transcription factors versus only one?

 

 

Now, put all of your items back in the Biomolecule Toolbox and begin again, and answer the following 2 questions.

1. What happens if you add 2 RNA Polymerases (one after the first, before transcription is complete), and then 2 ribosomes (one for each mRNA)?

 

 

2. What would be the benefit of working this way versus adding RNA Polymerase one at a time?

 

 

Click the yellow “Next Gene” box to begin working on the third gene. Can you remember the steps in order from your first trial? Try to see if you can!

 

 

3

 

 

 

Additional 4 Questions from the Expression Simulation:

1. What is gene expression?

 

 

2. What molecules are involved in gene expression? List them all and state the role of each.

 

 

 

 

 

 

3. What is the difference between the “regulatory region” and the “transcribed region”?

 

 

4. A student says that “ALL DNA codes for proteins.” Do you agree with her? Why or why not? Give evidence to support your answer.

Part 2: mRNA Simulation

At the bottom of the simulation page, click on the next simulation (it’s greyed out) called mRNA.

You should see a strand of DNA with a bunch of RNA Polymerases floating around. (If the RNA Polymerases are not moving, click the Play button.) Answer the following 7 questions.

1. Is mRNA being made?

 

2. In the Positive Transcription Factor box, slide the Concentration slider from NONE to just a tad (a couple millimeters or so) away from NONE. What do you notice is happening in the simulation now?

 

 

4

 

 

 

3. Move the Concentration slider all the way to HIGH. How does this affect what is happening in the simulation?

 

 

4. Leave the Concentration slider on HIGH but move the Affinity slider all the way to LOW. What happens? Move the Affinity slider to a midway setting? What happens now? Based on these observations, what do you think ​affinity​ means in this simulation?

 

 

 

 

 

 

5. Place both sliders in the Positive Transcription Factor box on the HIGH setting. ​Predict ​what will happen to the simulation if you were to move the RNA Polymerase affinity slider to the LOW position. Record your prediction.

 

 

 

6. Now, move the RNA Polymerase affinity slider to the LOW position and record your observations. Was your prediction correct?

 

7. Place all the sliders in the HIGH position. Check the box to add Negative Transcription Factors and place the concentration and affinity sliders on HIGH. How does this change transcription compared to without Negative Transcription Factors?

 

 

 

Continue to play around with the sliders until you can accurately predict how the change will affect transcription each time.

 

 

5

 

 

 

Additional 3 Questions from the mRNA Simulation:

1. What circumstances make the most mRNA? (What slider positions?)

2. What circumstances make the least mRNA? (What slider positions?)

 

3. Why would a cell need the option to make or not make a protein?

 

 

 

 

Part 3: Multiple Cells Simulation

At the bottom of the simulation page, click on the next simulation (it’s greyed out) called Multiple Cells.

Watch the generation of the graph called Average Protein Level vs. Time when one cell is working. If the graph does not automatically begin, then click the Play button at the bottom of the page. Answer the following 4 questions.

1. On the right side of the page, there are controls for Concentration, Affinity, and Degradation. (You need to click the green + to see the sliders.) Predict where you need to place each of the 3 sliders to achieve lots of protein. Record your predictions here:

a. The Concentration slider should be on LOW or on HIGH to achieve lots of protein?

 

b. The Affinity slider should be on LOW or on HIGH to achieve lots of protein?

 

c. The Degradation slider should be on LOW or on HIGH to achieve lots of protein?

 

6

 

 

 

2. Now, move the sliders into the positions you predicted to see if your predictions were correct. (NOTE: Each time you click “Refresh” to restart the graph, all of the sliders reset themselves to their original setting.) Then, explain why each setting – concentration, affinity, and degradation – makes sense for making lots of protein.

 

 

3. Why would a protein need to be degraded?

 

 

 

4. Think back to last week’s lab – Lactase Enzyme Lab. Give an example from that lab of a time when it would be necessary to make a lot of one type of protein.

 

Part 4: Effects of Mutations on Gene Expression You have learned this week that cells use the two-step process of transcription and translation to transform a protein-coding DNA sequence into a chain of amino acids that makes up a protein. The resulting chain of amino acids will fold into a three-dimensional protein structure that defines the phenotype. Imagine that the following DNA sequence is part of a protein-coding gene. Use this sequence to answer the questions that follow.

… G G A T G C C G C T C T G C A A C T A C…

A) What is the ​complementary DNA sequence​ to the DNA sequence above? ​Hint: look back to your reading and lesson notes to recall the pairing rules for nucleotides A, T, G, and C if you need to!

 

 

B) What is the ​mRNA sequence​ transcribed from the DNA sequence from ​Part A​? ​Hint: your answer below should start with the letter ​G​ and not ​C​!

 

 

C) What ​corresponding amino acid sequence​ is translated from the mRNA sequence from ​Part (B)​? Use the genetic code from the lesson or the one posted in the lab. ​Remember that your amino acid sequence should always start with the ​START codon​!

 

D) For the following scenarios (i)-(iii), identify the type of mutation that has occurred (single base-pair substitution or frameshift mutation) to our original sequence AND the new amino acid chain that results

7

 

 

 

from such a mutation. Complete the same sequence from complementary DNA sequence, then mRNA sequence, and then corresponding amino acid sequence like what you did in Parts A, B, and C above!

(i) The 4​th​ C in the original sequence is mutated to a T:

… G G A T G C C G C T ​T​ T G C A A C T A C …

Type of mutation:

New amino acid chain:

 

(ii) An extra C is inserted into the original sequence:

… G G A T G C C G C ​C​ T C T G C A A C T A C …

Type of mutation:

New amino acid chain:

 

(iii) The 5​th​ C in the original sequence is mutated to A:

… G G A T G C C G C T C T G ​A​ A A C T A C …

 

Type of mutation:

New amino acid chain:

 

E) At the end of translation, an amino acid chain will subsequently fold into a protein with a specific structure and function.

 

(i) Of the three mutations described in part (D), which mutation will cause the ​least ​change to protein function? Briefly explain your reasoning.

 

(ii) Which mutation would you expect to significantly alter protein function? Briefly explain your reasoning.

Biology Lab Gene Expression

 
"Looking for a Similar Assignment? Get Expert Help at an Amazing Discount!"